The right
of people (including ‘mature minors’ and the very old) to make informed
decision and formally consent or refuse to consent to treatment in health care
contexts is now widely recognized as a basic ethical and legal precondition to
conscientious medical practice’ and the conscientious provision of nursing care
(Dicken & cook, 2004).
Of all the patients’ rights which might be claimed in a given health care context, however, none is perhaps more challenging to power, authority and sometimes the integrity of attending health professionals than the patient’s right to make informed choices about his/her care and treatment. The doctrine of informed consent, although having a profound ethical dimension, is essentially a legal doctrine developed partially out of recognition of patient’s right to self-determination and partially out of the nurse’s or other health professionals duty to give the patient information about proposed treatment so as to provide him or her with the opportunity of making an “informed” or “rational” choice as to whether to undergo the treatment (Beauchamp & Childress, 2001).
Of all the patients’ rights which might be claimed in a given health care context, however, none is perhaps more challenging to power, authority and sometimes the integrity of attending health professionals than the patient’s right to make informed choices about his/her care and treatment. The doctrine of informed consent, although having a profound ethical dimension, is essentially a legal doctrine developed partially out of recognition of patient’s right to self-determination and partially out of the nurse’s or other health professionals duty to give the patient information about proposed treatment so as to provide him or her with the opportunity of making an “informed” or “rational” choice as to whether to undergo the treatment (Beauchamp & Childress, 2001).
In distinguishing the differences between a
legal and moral approach to informed consent, Faden and Beauchamp (1986)
explain that legal law’s approach to
informed consent ‘springs from pragmatic theory’, which focuses more on a
physician/ nurses duty to disclose information to patients and not to injure
them. By the contrast, moral philosophy’s approach to informed consent springs
from a right to make an autonomous choice’. Similarly, the moral demand to
respect autonomy is clearly the prime motivator of the health professional’s
duty to disclose information, and the moral principle of non-maleficence is the
prime motivator of the health professional’s duty not to harm or injure
patients. Informed consent is: “The
process of agreeing to take part in a study based on access to all relevant and
easily digestible information about what participation means, in particular, in
terms of harms and benefits.” (Parahoo,
2006).In this paper informed consent and ethical principlism, elements of an
informed and valid consent and role of physicians and mainly nurses in getting valid
consent will critically discussed.
Informed consent also rests heavily on moral
principles or ethical principlism both for its content and justification as an
action guide. The principle of respect for person is the most important moral
principle to justify getting the informed consent. The respect for Person has at least two
ethical considerations. The first is
that the client/ patient who are undergoing elective treatment or surgery be
treated as an autonomous being—a person who makes decisions or deliberates for
her/himself about personal goals and then acts upon them. The autonomy which
demands respects for patients as self- determining choosers, and justifies
allowing them the option of accepting risks. The second is that those persons
who are not able to make and carry out decisions for themselves, such as
children or very older people or those who have a certain kind of mental
disorder must be protected from coercion by others and from activities that
harm them. How much to protect them is
related to the risk of harm and likelihood of benefit to them. In
medical treatment or, nursing intervention respect for person’ demands that
participants enter into a medical or nursing care program voluntarily and with
good information about the treatment goals. Another moral principle related to
informed consent is beneficence which demands the maximization of patient wellbeing
via consent processes (Johnstone, 2009).
In addition,
justice and non-maleficence are an essential principles related to informed
consent. The justice- which demands fairness and that, patients not be unduly
or intolerably burdened by consent processes. The moral principle
non-maleficence- which demands the protection of patients from battery,
assault, trespass, exploitation and other harms that may result from inadequate
or inappropriate consent processes (including the inadequate or inappropriate
disclosure of information). Despite of autonomy is one of the important moral principles
to getting consent however it should be noted that while autonomy is a value
underlying the doctrine of informed consent it is not the value, nor an
absolute value. As Faden and Beauchamp (1986) point out, at best autonomy is
only a prima-face value, and to regard it as having overriding value would be
both historically and culturally odd. This is not to say that autonomy does not
have a significant place in a moral approach to informed consent. It merely
means that it does not have a sole place, and can be justly restricted by other
competing moral principles.
In addition, justification of informed consent
especially for research purpose is associated with consequentialism. The Consequentialist reasons are grounded in the conviction that the action
with the best overall expected consequences is, generally, the action we ought
to take. The primary consequentialist reason for adopting a principle of
informed consent, then, is that doing so has the best expected consequences
compared with alternatives. This view can be supported by a number of
contentions, including the following:
A) Obtaining subjects’ informed consent to participation tends to
increase their Adherence to the
protocol, and hence the quality of the research and purposed treatment.
B) Since investigators are not always
able to identify the risks their research or may pose to subjects, a process of
informed consent provides the benefit of an additional layer of risk review
tailored to the interests of the individual subject.
C) Affirming a principle of informed
consent is likely to foster public trust of the research community; without
such trust the research enterprise could not flourish.
This could be argued from both
utilitarian and deontological perspectives. The utilitarian approach could be
based on non-maleficence; society expects and trust health care professionals
to be truthful and to respect individual persons to maintain good client/
professional relationship. Trust between the client and the professional is
essential. Similarly, from deontological perspective, based on respect for
personhood, people are entitled to practice autonomy. To be able to make
rational decisions knowledge or information is an essential component. In legal
basis of informed consent is not, in itself, a criminal offense it could result
in a charge of criminal assault or a suit of negligence.
When we
discuss about an informed and valid consent, its components are standards of
that consent is either informed or valid or not. It is generally recognized
within medical or bioethics that disclosure, comprehension, voluntariness,
competence, and consent itself from the analytical components concepts of
informed consent (Faden & Beauchamp, 1986). Morally speaking, consent
should be regarded fully informed; it must satisfy number of criteria,
including those relating to information aspect and those relating to the giving
consent itself. Beauchamp and Childress (2001) argues that for consent to be
informed, there must be a disclosure of all relevant information (including
benefits and risks) and patient must fully understand (comprehend) both the
information which has been given and the implications of giving consent. Pedroni and Pimple (2001) centered that three
different standards for disclosing information have evolved in legal and
bioethical contexts:
1)
A professional practice standard, which requires disclosure only of the
information that professionals typically provide;
2)
A reasonable person standard, which requires disclosure of the
information that a thoughtful layperson would consider relevant to such a
decision; and
3) A subjective standard, which
requires disclosure of the information considered to be material to the decision by the
specific person who must make
In addition, if one goal of informed
consent is to ensure that patients have sufficient information to be able to
determine which decision about their medical or nursing care compliance is most
compatible with their individual interests and values, then a subjective standard of
disclosure would seem to be the most appropriate. However, it is impossible for
health professionals to know in advance what information each potential subject
of a given care will take to be relevant. In practice, the best way to
facilitate informed consent may be to design consent forms and other
informational materials to satisfy a reasonable
person standard, supplemented by conversations intended to elicit
and answer any questions that are not otherwise addressed (Pedroni &
Pimple, 2001). Secondly, the consent must be voluntarily given (i.e. the
patient must be free of coercion or manipulation), and lastly the patient must
be competent to consent (i.e. both rational and prudent). Even this requirement;
however seems too very strong, virtually every decision is controlled to some
extent to others. So if the concept of voluntariness is ever it have any
application in real world, it will have to consist in substantially
non-controlled decisions and actions rather than complete freedom.
Beauchamp and Faden (1986) point out “control
is external through influences…. But not all influences are controlling.” The
three controlling are identified and suggested, first of all, coercion is
external always fully controlling and thus it is incompatible with informed
consent, secondly, persuasion is never controlling and is always compatible
with informed consent and finally, manipulation is double standard it helps
client to change the attitude and other psychological and emotional components
of a person through information therefore it is sometimes be compatible with
informed consent sometimes not. It is most important that, informed consent is
based upon the premise that a patient has the legal right to make his or her
own decisions on medical treatment. The law presumes that an adult is competent
to make a treatment choice, i.e., has the mental capacity to consent to or
refuse treatment. However, minors generally do not have the legal right to
consent. The issue of competency is, however, controversial and complicated.
This is because there is no substantial agreement on the characteristics of a
competent person, or on how competency should be measured. Nor is there any
legal test of competency that commands general acceptance’ (Gert et al 1997). Decision
Making Capacity addition to having adequate
information, understanding, and freedom from controlling influences, informed
consent requires that potential subjects have the capacity to make a decision
about participation. That is, they must have the ability to determine whether
participation or non-participation is most consistent with their authentic
preferences, goals and values. As a precondition of decision making capacity,
persons giving consent must have reasonably stable preferences, goals
and values with which they genuinely identify, suggesting that a certain level
of maturity is necessary (Pedroni & Pimple, 2001).
By the contrast, obtaining informed consent is depends on different
situation. Some Exceptions
to the obligation to obtain an informed consent include the following
(Princeton insurance, 2009).
1. Emergency—the patient presents with a life-threatening injury or
illness requiring immediate attention and is unable to communicate and there is
no time to obtain consent from another appropriate person. Only care that is
medically necessary to remedy the emergency situation is permitted.
2. Waiver by Patient—the patient may expressly waive the
right to be informed of the risks and alternatives to treatment. A patient’s
waiver of informed consent is treatment-specific; informed consent must be
obtained for other proposed treatments or procedures.
3. Therapeutic Privilege—disclosure of all known risks of
treatment believed to cause the patient the risk of significant harm (typically
psychological). The patient should be evaluated by a provider not otherwise
involved in his/her care before invoking this exception. Permission from the
patient to discuss the information with his or her family should be sought.
In clinical care or community setting
the heart of nursing is the patient. We have discussed so many issues about
informed consent so far. In this context nurses have much to contribute to the
informed consent/decision making debate. It is also clear that nurses play a
great role as an advocator for patients. Further, it is clear that the nursing
profession needs too much greater attention to doctrine of informed consent and
its moral implications for nurses- not least the duties it imposes on nurses to
obtain patients informed consent to nursing care and nursing procedures, and
the issues it raises concerning nursing paternalism (Johnstone, 2009). It is perhaps important to emphasize that,
although the doctrine of informed consent has traditionally been discussed
primarily in regard to medical care and treatment, the underlying moral
principles and values and moral requirements of this doctrine are apply equally
to other kind of health profession including nursing care and procedures. This
is because nursing is not so different or less exempt than any other health
care professionals from the moral standards governing consent procedures,
including the demands to (Adopted from Johnstone, 2009)
·
Disclose
all relevant information necessary for an informed decision about purposed
nursing cares and procedures.
·
To
ensure the patient properly understand the information and implication of
giving consent
·
Ensure
that the consent is patients’ rational choice (nurses don not coerce or
manipulate the patient into giving consent).
·
To
ensure that patient is competent to make informed choice and if not, that the
surrogate decision-making on the patients’ behalf.
The
issue in patient nurse relationship during informed consent should be based on
paternalistic unlike medical paternalism. However these issues both stand as
fertile ground for further debate!
Conclusion
Informed consent is in modern medical
and nursing profession is an essential component when delivering a care to a
patient. Giving proper information to the patients about their medical and nursing
care is health care professional’s legal and moral obligation. It is nurses’
duty to provide proper and adequate information to the patient about
intervening treatment and other medical procedures. Morally providing
information to the patient is beneficence and non-maleficence and treating a
patient with fairness. However, certain type of
information should not be disclosed in particular situation like
emergency situation, wavier by patient and therapeutic privilege. The main
reason for informed consent is to treat patient is as a sovereign body and
respect his right of self-determination and partially out of the nurse’s or
other health professionals duty to give the patient information about proposed
treatment so as to provide him or her with the opportunity of making an
“informed” or “rational” choice as to whether to undergo the treatment. In a
clinical setting nurse should establish a good therapeutic relation based on
honesty which is only effective when there is assertiveness between patient and
nurses.
Work cited
1.
Beauchamp,
T., L & Childress, j (2001) Principle
of biomedical ethics (5th Ed.). Oxford University press, New
York
2.
Dicken,
B & Cook, R (2004) Ethical and legal issues in reproductive health: dimensions
of informed consent to treatment. International Journal of Gynecology and
Obstetrics, vol. 85 No.3, pp. 309-14.
3.
Faden,
R. R & Beauchamp, T., L (1986) A
history and theory of informed consent. Oxford University Press, New York
4.
Gert,
B., Culver, C & Clouser, K., D (1997) Bioethics: a return to fundamentals.
Oxford University Press, New York
5.
Johnstone,
M-j (2009) Bioethics: a nursing
Perspective (5th ed.) Churchill Livingstone, Elsevier
6.
Parahoo,
K (2006) Nursing research: principles, process and issues (2nd edition),
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
7.
Pedroni,
J.A., & Pimple, K.D. (2001). A brief introduction to informed consent in
research with human subjects. Retrieved June 27, 2007, from poynter.indiana.edu/sas/res/ic.pdf.
8.
Princeton
insurance (2005) Reducing risk: informed
consent (revised in 2005). A Publication on HealthCare Risk Management from
Princeton Insurance from http//www.pinsco.com/downloads/...risk/NJ.Informed.Consent.June05.pdf
No comments:
Post a Comment